Summary:
Tupper
(2008) argues that Canada shows a little consideration for the continuing
disappearances and murders of Aboriginal girls and women in the country. As
Tupper (2008) notices that women have been marginalized, she decides to discuss
citizenship, democracy and education in relation to women. Although Tupper
(2008) agrees that education improves people's life, she argues that education
has been used as a tool for "cultural transmission", "cultural genocide",
and "the maintenance of the status of quo which privileges certain
socio-cultural groups at the expense of others" (p. 67). Therefore, Tupper
(2008) believes that democratic education has been colonized. In this chapter,
Tupper (2008) endeavors to achieve three goals. First, "using feminist
socio-political theory", Tupper (2008) "challenge[s] the assumption
that democracy exists, particularly as it relates to the lives and experiences
of girls and women in schools and in the broader society" (p. 67). Second,
Tupper (2008) "examine[s] how women are discursively produced by universal
conceptions of citizenship, that are, at the core, inherently masculine"
(p. 67). Finally, Tupper (2008) "interrogate[s] the extent to which
citizenship education, a significant goal of schooling is used to perpetuate,
rather than disrupt, the fallacy of democratic education" (p. 67).
Tupper
(2008) agrees with Pateman (1989) on the subject that democracy has never
included women. Pateman (1989) argues that "women have never been and
still are not admitted as full and equal members and citizens in any country
known as a 'democracy'" (as cited in Tupper, 2008, p. 68). Although a lot
of political theorists, as Pateman (1989) highlights, appear to acknowledge
that in democracy people are all involved despite of their differences, Pateman
(1989) argues that "the social contract is a fraternal pace that
constitutes civil society as a patriarchal or masculine order" (as cited
in Tupper, 2008, p. 68). Additionally, Tupper (2008) agrees with Pateman (1989)
that both public spaces (civil society) and private ones (non-civil society)
are inherently masculine. In the public domain, the characters of 'good'
citizens such as reason, self-determination, and individual potential, are, as Jubas
(2006) argues, first gendered and then valued (Tupper, 2008). Pateman (1989)
states that the "civil body politic is fashioned after the image of the
male individual who is constituted through the separation of civil society from
women" (as cited in Tupper, 2008, p. 69). Although the liberals argue that
social inequalities are irrelevant to political equality, Pateman (1989)
maintains that these two aspects are integrally connected (Tupper, 2008). For
example, the right to vote and the ability to campaign for a certain political
party do not remove inequality (Tupper, 2008). Thus, Tupper (2008) argues that
as women face social inequalities, they become unable to operate any political
agency. Similar to the public sphere, the private realm is an inherently
gendered space in which women are less important and less valued (Tupper,
2008). Tupper (2008) uses Helen Betty Osborne, who was murdered by four white
men, as an example demonstrating how women are disenfranchised in private
spaces. Moreover, Tupper (2008) argues that the racializing and gendering of
women's identities make these women become 'second-class citizens'. Tupper
(2008) questions the veracity of citizenship and argues that citizenship is
falsely universal, complex and layered as it rests upon both difference and
sameness. By way of example, Tupper (2008) asks "if security of person is
a right that all Canadians are entitled to, then why are some members of the
population less likely to enjoy this right than others [for example the aboriginal
women]?" (p. 69) Like Pateman (1989), Lister (1997) criticizes the liberal
democracies for the "binary thinking that constrains the articulation of
women's claims to citizenship" (as cited in Tupper, 2008, p. 70). Tupper
(2008) is particularly concerned with citizenship in terms of both status and
practice. As status, Tupper (2008) argues that liberal democracies promote what
she calls the "meta-narrative of universal citizenship" which
"accepts that democracy exists, despite feminist claims to the contrary,
and accepts that citizenship exists universally" (p. 70). Tupper (2008)
emphasizes that status and practice are often not seen as independent factors
because as long as a person is a citizen (status) he/she can be fully involved
as a citizen (practice). However, this is precisely where the meta-narrative
collapses (Tupper, 2008). Tupper (2008) also stresses that the practices of
citizenship are determined by different factors such as gender, race, class,
culture, ethnicity, religion, and sexual orientation. Additionally, Tupper
(2008) believes that this meta-narrative perpetuates the gendering of
citizenship. As women are thought to be mostly emotional and passionate beings
who are unable to be rational and reasonable, they are historically believed to
be incapable of enacting citizenship which requires rationality and
reasonableness (Tupper, 2008). Therefore, Tupper (2008) emphasizes that
"[w]omen's citizenship could only ever be second-class as long as they
differed, by virtue of being women, from men, and men were used as the standard
or norm for understanding citizenship" (p. 70). Moreover, Phillips (2000)
argues that it is not only the very reality of being women but also the
inequality produced by the differences between men and women that makes women
unable to become fully engaged citizens in both public and private spaces
(Tupper, 2008).
In
what follows, Tupper (2008) discusses the degree to which schools and school
curriculum advance the meta-narrative of universal citizenship which
perpetuates "second class" citizenship (p. 72). Tupper (2008) argues
that as citizenship objectives are made universal through curriculum, the
differences between students are made impossible to see. Additionally, while
teachers endeavor to achieve the goals of citizenship education for all
students, they "may pay less attention or no attention to the lived
experiences of difference their students bring to the classroom" (Tupper,
2008, p. 72). Moreover, although Tupper (2008) recognizes the need for establishing
the same goals concerning students' knowledge, skills and attitudes, she
emphasizes that these objectives should never reverse the lived experiences of
students produced by their race, culture, gender, and class. Tupper (2008) uses
the Canadian school curriculum as an example to show how the objectives or
rationales of some school curriculum often seem neutral when they are actually
partial. Tupper (2008) highlights that "standardizing educational goals
does not mean education is democratic. Rather, quite the opposite" (p.
73). Additionally, Tupper (2008) explains how schools and curriculum are used
to disguise the false universalism of citizenship. The stories of violence
contained in the Stolen Sisters Report emphasize the failures of democracy for
Aboriginal women, as well as question the veracity of citizenship (Tupper,
2008).
Assessment,
critique and questions:
I
personally found Tupper's (2008) chapter an interesting read as it discusses
one of the most pressing issues in the Omani society nowadays. Her point that Aboriginal
women have become second-class citizens through the racializing and gendering
of their identities resonates with me because it makes me think about the
Eastern world's view of Western women. In Oman, people, particularly women,
believe that both men and women have equal rights in the Western world.
However, reading Tupper's (2008) chapter, I realize that there is
discrimination between men and women, in particular Aboriginal ladies, because
of gender. This strong bias against women conflicts with how Omani ladies
perceive Canadian women. As Omani women consider Canada to be a democratic
country, they think that both men and women obtain the same rights and
responsibilities as citizens of Canada. However, Tupper (2008) argues that
this is not always the case. I personally agree with Pateman (1989) that
"women have never been and still are not admitted as full and equal
members and citizens in any country known as a 'democracy'" (as cited in
Tupper, 2008, p. 68).
At
the beginning of the chapter, Tupper (2008) explains the context in which this
chapter has emerged, clearly states the main arguments she wants to advance,
and briefly describe the organization of her chapter. Thus, I found that this
chapter is easy to follow. Moreover, Tupper (2008) uses real life stories taken
from the Stolen Sisters Report along with examples of school curriculum in
order to support her arguments. Additionally, I think that the questions,
Tupper (2008) asks throughout the chapter, stimulate the readers to think
critically and guide them through the content of the chapter. On the other
hand, I think that Tupper's (2008) chapter constitutes a one-sided
representation of women in citizenship, democracy and education as Tupper
(2008) rests upon only female scholars' point of view to support her arguments.
Moreover, Tupper (2008) mainly cites the work of just three researchers in her
chapter, thus I personally think that her conclusions might not be conclusive.
Furthermore, while Tupper (2008) criticizes Canada for treating women as
second-class citizens, she does not suggest any solutions to this problem. Additionally,
Tupper (2008) uses the example of the murders of aboriginal women in Canada to overgeneralize
the idea that all Canadian women are mistreated by men and are unable to obtain
the same rights and responsibilities as men. Reading Tupper's (2008) chapter,
the following questions came to my mind:
1.
Do
Canadian women, other than Aboriginal ladies, have equal rights with men?
2.
Do
Aboriginal women, as citizens of Canada, obtain the same rights and
responsibilities as men?
3.
Do
schools perpetuate the assumption that women's citizenship is second-class by
excluding the discussion about the murders of aboriginal women from their
curriculum?
4.
Do
you agree with Pateman (1989) and Lister (1997) that "women have never
experienced citizenship in the same way as men" (as cited in Tupper, 2008,
p. 71)?
5.
Do you
agree with Phillips (2000) that "equality depends on sameness" (as
cited in Tupper, 2008, p. 71)?
6.
Is
democracy, including democratic education, really colonized in Canada?
Reference:
Tupper, J. (2008). Feminism confronts democracy: Challenging
universal citizenship and democratic education. In A. Abdi & G. Richardson
(Eds.). Decolonizing democratic education
(pp.67-76). Rotterdam: Sense.
Hi Said, some of your questions really resonate with me. While we are considering equal rights, do the "whiteness" women and the "visible minority" women have the same equal rights with men? How do we reinforce the democratic education from curriculum perspective?
ReplyDeleteHi Said, I really liked your piece. I also agree with Pateman, because when you look around at most of the democratic countries, the people predominantly making decisions are men. So how can choices be made to try and create equal citizenship for women if women are not the ones making decisions about them.
ReplyDeleteThank you for the thorough summary, Said! I appreciated your discussion of this reading (and its arguments) in relation to Oman and how (Western) citizenship is perceived by many Omani citizens. I found it really interesting that you noticed Tupper relies on female scholars, though this does not really surprise me as I don't find that many men generally focus on female citizenship (I could be wrong!). It is a great point, however, that she probably could use some more sources/citations to support her arguments. As we have discussed in class, it really is a shame that most scholars are able to highlight the problems we are facing but offer little to no solution or roadmaps to (start to) remedy the problems.
ReplyDelete